Skepticism, theology, and science: the case of earth’s motion

Authors

  • Carlos Solís Santos Departamento de Lógica, historia y filosofía de la ciencia, Facultad de Filosofía, Universidad Nacional de Educación a Distancia

DOI:

https://doi.org/10.3989/asclepio.2015.10

Keywords:

Earth’s motion, Cosmology, Theology, Skepticism, Omnipotentia Dei absoluta

Abstract


The Omnipotentia Dei absoluta thesis (any non-contradictory state of fact is possible) was used by theologians as a skeptical argument against any scientific claim unwarranted by biblical exegesis. Mathematical astronomy was bound to build models of data based on physically sound hypothesis acceptable to theology. Fourteenth century theologian Nicolas Oresme weighted the arguments pro Earth and Heavens rotation. Being an expert in mathematics and natural philosophy, concluded the higher plausibility of Earth’s rotation, but skeptical considerations declared those arguments insufficient and the opinion false for scriptural reasons. Seventeenth century setting was much different: Reform induced an increase of catholic fundamentalism, while Galileo’s physical arguments in support of Copernicanism, together with his refutation of Ptolemaic cosmology due to Venus phases, turned the skeptical balance between both systems untenable. Roman theologians being this time ignoramuses in mathematics and physics, condemned Galileo and declared heliocentrism false, physically absurd, and formally heretic.

Downloads

Download data is not yet available.

References

Belarmino, Roberto (1984), The Louvain Lectures (Lectiones Lovanienses) of Bellarmine and the Autograph Copy of his 1616 Declaration to Galileo, U. Baldini y G. V. Coyne (eds.). Ciudad del Vaticano, Vatican Observatory Publications.

Beltrán Marí, Antonio (2006), Talento y poder. Historia de las relaciones entre Galileo y la Iglesia católica, Pamplona, Laetoli.

Bianchi, Luca (2000), "Interventi divini, miracoli e ipotesi soprannaturali nel Dialogo di Galileo". En: Canziani, G., Granada, M. A. y Zarka Y. C. (eds.), Potentia Dei. L'onnipotenza divina nel pensiero dei secoli XVI e XVII, Milán, Franco Angeli, pp. 239-251.

Bianchi, Luca (2001), "Agostino Oreggi, qualificatore del Dialogo, e i limiti della conoscenza scientifica". En: Montesinos, J. y Solís, C. (eds.), pp. 575-84. PMid:11258440

Blackwell, Richard J. (1991), Galileo, Bellarmine, and the Bible, Notre Dame, University of Notre Dame Press.

Buridán, Jean (1942), Quaestiones super libris quattor de caelo et mundo, E. Moody (ed.). Cambridge, Mass, The Mediaeval Academy of America. Hay reediciones hasta 2012.

Buridán, Jean (2000), Summulae de Dialectica, G. Klima (ed.). New Haven, Yale University Press.

Clagett, Marshall (1959), The Science of Mechanics in the Middle Ages, Madison, The University of Wisconsin Press. PMCid:PMC1613508

Clagett, Marshall (1968), Nicole Oresme and the Medieval Geometry of Qualities and Motions, Madison, The University of Wisconsin Press.

Clavius, Christoph (1611), Commentarium In Sphaeram Ioannis de Sacro Bosco & Astrolabium. En Christophori Clavii Opera Mathematica, III, Moguntiae, Antonii Hierat, excudebat Reinhardus Eltz [Ioannes Volmari].

Copérnico, Nicolás (1973), Opera omnia, 4 vols. Varsovia, Officina Publica Libris Scientificis Edendis.

Crombie, Alistair C. (1959), The History of Science from Augustine to Galileo. Nueva York, Dover Publications. Hay traducción espa-ola, Historia de la ciencia: De San Agustín a Galileo, Madrid, Alianza, 1974.

Denifle, Henricus (1889), Chartularium Universitatis Parisiensis, tomo I. París, Ex typis Fratrum Delalain.

Funkenstein, Amos (1986), Theology and the Scientific Imagination from the Middle Ages to the Seventeenth Century, Princeton University Press.

Galilei, Galileo (1890-1909), Le opere di Galileo Galilei, Antonio Favaro (ed.), 20 vols. Florencia, G. Barbèra.

Grant, Edward (1962), "Late Medieval Thought, Copernicus, and the Scientific Revolution", Journal of the History of Ideas, XXIII (2), pp. 197-220. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2708155

Grant, Edward (1988), "Nicole Oresme on Certitude in Science and Pseudo-Science", en Soufrin, P. y Segonds, A. P. (eds.), Nicolas Oresme: Tradition et innovation chez un intellectuel du XIVe siècle, París, Les Belles Lettres, pp. 31-43.

Grant, Edward (1993), "Jean Buridan and Nicole Oresme on Natural Knowledge", Vivarium, XXXI (1), pp. 84-105. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/156853493X00105

Klima, Gyula (2009), John Buridan. Oxford University Press.

Lattis, James M (1994), Between Copernicus and Galileo. Christopher Clavius and the Collapse of Ptolemaic Cosmology, The University of Chicago Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.7208/chicago/9780226469263.001.0001

López Prada, Fernando (2014), Usar la razón para confundir a la razón. La epistemología de Nicolás Oresme, trabajo de fin de Master. Madrid, Facultad de Filosofía, UNED.

Maier, Anneliese (1955), "Die naturphilosophische Bedeutung der scholastischen Impetus-theorien", Scholastik, XXX, pp. 321-43. Traducción inglesa en el Capítulo 4 de S. D. Sargent (ed.), On the Threshold of Exact Science. Selected Writtings of Anneliese Maier on Late Medieval Natural Philosophy, Filadelfia, University of Pennsylvania Press, 1982, pp. 77-102.

Marx, Karl (1852), "Der achtzehnte Brumaire des Louis Bonaparte", Die Revolution, Eine Zeitschrift in zwanglosen Heften von Joseph Weydemeyer, Nueva York.

Montesinos, José y Solís, Carlos (eds.) (2001), Largo campo di filosofare Eurosymposium Galileo 2001. La Orotava, Fundación Canaria la Orotava de Historia de la ciencia.

Oresme, Nicolás (1952), Livre de divinacions y Tractatus contra iudiciarios asrtronomos. En: Coopland, George William (ed.), Nicole Oresme and the Astrologers, Liverpool, Harvard University Press, pp. 50-121 y pp. 123-41.

Oresme, Nicolás (1966), De proportionibus proportionum and Ad pauca respicientes, Edward Grant (ed.). Madison, The University of Wisconsin Press.

Oresme, Nicolás (1968), Le livre du ciel et du monde, A. D. Menut y A. J. Denomy (eds.). Madison, The University of Wisconsin Press.

Oresme, Nicolás (1971), Nicole Oresme and the Kinematics of Circular Motion: Tractatus de commensurabilitate vel incommensurabilitate motuum celi, E. Grant (ed.). Madison, The University of Wisconsin Press.

Oresme, Nicolás (1973), "Quodlibeta" En: B. Hansen (ed.), Nicole Oresme and the marvels of nature: a critical edition of his Quodlibeta with English translation and commentary, Princeton University Press.

Oresme, Nicolás (1976), "Quaestio contra divinatores horoscopios", Archives d’Histoire Doctrinale et Littéraire du Moyen Age, París, Vrin, pp. 201-310.

Oresme, Nicolás (2007), De visione stellarum, D. Burton (ed.). Leiden, Brill.

Piché, David (1999), La condamnation parisienne de 1277, nouvelle e’dition du texte latin, traduction, introduction et commentaire par David Piché avec la collaboration de Claude Lafleur. París, Vrin.

Ptolomeo, Claudio (1984), Almagest, G. J. Toomer (ed.). Londres, Duckworth.

Solís, Carlos (2001), "La cosmología oculta de Galileo". En: Montesinos, José y Solís Santos, Carlos (coords.), Largo campo di filosofare Eurosymposium Galileo 2001, pp. 357-379.

Van Helden, Albert (1985), Measuring the Universe. Cosmic Dimensions from Aristarchus to Halley, The University of Chicago Press.

Weijers, Olga (2005), Le travail intellectuel à la Faculté des arts de Paris: textes et maîtres (c. 1200-1500), Turnhout, Brepols.

Zú-iga, Diego de (1584), In Job commentaria, Toledo, Johannes Rodericus.

Published

2015-06-30

How to Cite

Solís Santos, C. (2015). Skepticism, theology, and science: the case of earth’s motion. Asclepio, 67(1), p084. https://doi.org/10.3989/asclepio.2015.10

Issue

Section

Studies